Смекни!
smekni.com

Taoism Essay Research Paper Classical Chinese theory (стр. 2 из 3)

to sustain Mencius? unified moral empire. The LATER MOHISTS became skeptical

of the neutral status of these allegedly "natural" heart-mind states.

They noted that even a thief may claim that his behavior was natural. They

watered down the conventionalism of Mozi by appealing to objectively accessible

similarities and differences in nature. Our language ought to reflect these

clusters of similarity. They did little epistemology especially of the senses,

but supposedly, like Mozi, would have appealed to the testimony ordinary people

relying on their "eyes and ears." Others (See ZHUANGZI) insisted that

any apparent patterns of similarity and difference were always perspectival and

relative to some prior purpose, standards or value attitude. Linguistics did

shape heart-mind attitudes but neither reliably or accurately carves the world

into its real parts. The Later Mohists had given a cluster of definitions of zhi

(to know). One of these seemed close to consciousness?or rather to point to

the lack of any such concept. Zhi was the capacity to know. In dreaming the zhi

did not zhi and we took (something) as so. They analyzed the key function of the

heart-mind as the capacity to discriminate linguistic intention. Zhuangzi takes

a step beyond Laozi in his theory of emotions. Zhuangzi discusses the passions

and emotions that were raw, pre-social inputs from reality. He suggested a

pragmatic attitude toward them?we cannot know what purpose they have, but

without them, there would be no reference for the "I." Without the

‘I’, there would be neither choosing nor objects of choice. Like Hume, he argued

that while we have these inputs and feel there must be some organizing

"true ruler," we get no input (qing) from any such ruler. We simply

have the inputs themselves (happiness, anger, sorrow, joy, fear). We cannot

suppose that the physical heart is such a ruler, because it is no more natural

than the other organs and joints of the body. Training and history condition a

heart?s judgments. Ultimately, even Mencius? shi-fei (this-not this) are

input to the xin. Our experience introduces them relative to our position and

past assumptions. They are not objective or neutral judgments. XUNZI also

concentrated on issues related to philosophy of mind though in the context of

moral and linguistic issues. He initiated some important and historically

influential developments in the classical theory. His most famous (and textually

suspect) doctrine is "human nature is evil." While he clearly wanted

to distance himself from Mencius, the slogan at best obscures the deep affinity

between their respective views of human nature and mind. Xunzi seems to have

drawn both from the tradition advocating cultivating heart-mind and from the

focused theory of language. This produced a tense hybrid theory that filled out

the original Confucian picture on how conventions and language program the

heart-mind. Xunzi made the naturalism explicit. Human guiding discourse takes

place in the context of a three-tier universe?tian (heaven-nature) di

(earth-sustenance) and ren (the social realm). He gave humans a special place in

the ?chain of nature,’ but not based on reason. Animals shared the capacity

for zhi (knowledge). What distinguishes humans is their yi (morality) which is

grounded on the ability to bian (distinguish). Presumably, the latter ability is

unique among animals with knowledge because it is short-hand for the ability to

construct and abide by conventions?conventional distinctions or language. One

of Xunzi?s naturalistic justifications for Confucian conventional rituals is

economic. Ritual distinctions guide people?s desires so that society can

manage scarcity. Only those with high status will learn to seek scarce goods.

His departure from Mencius thus seems to lie in seeing human morality as more

informed or "filled-out" by historical conventional distinctions.

These are the products of reflection and artifice, not nature. However, in other

ways Xunzi seems to edge closer to Mencius. He also presents ritual as part of

the structure of the world?implicit in the heaven-earth natural context. One

natural line of explanation is this: while thought creates the correct

conventions, nature sets the concrete conditions of scarcity and human traits

that determine what conventions will be best for human flourishing. Return to

Outline Historical Developments: Han Cosmology The onset of the philosophical

dark age, brought on by Qin Dynasty repression followed by Han dynasty policies

resulted in a bureaucratic, obscurant Confucian orthodoxy. The Qin thus buried

the technical ideas informing philosophy of mind along with the active thinkers

who understood them. The ontology of the eclectic scholasticism that emerged was

essentially religious and superstitious. It was, however, overtly materialist

(assuming Qi (ether, matter) is material). So the implicit philosophy of mind of

the few philosophically inclined thinkers during the period tended toward a

vague materialism. The Han further developed the five-element (five phases)

version of materialism. They postulated a correlative pentalogy linking

virtually every system of classification that occurred to them. The scheme

included the organs of the body and the virtues. Interpretation and analysis of

"correlative" reasoning is a controversial subject. From here, the

mental correlations look more like a frequency selection from the psychological

lexicon than a product of philosophical reflection, observation or causal

theory. The Yin-yang analysis also had mental correlates. Following Xunzi,

Orthodox Han Confucians tended to treat qing (reality:desires) as yin (typically

negative). The yang (value positive) counterpart was xing (human moral nature).

The most important development of the period was the emergence a compromise

Confucian view of mind?s role in morality. It eventually informed and

dominated the scholastic Neo-Confucianism of the much later Sung to Qing

dynasties. The small book known as the Doctrine of the Mean gave it an

influential formulation. It presents the heart-mind as a homeostasis-preserving

input output device. The heart-mind starts in a state of tranquillity. The

account leaves open whether this is a result of ideally structured moral input,

resolution of inner conflicts, or the absence of (distorting) content. Xunzi?s

view of the empty, unified and still mind seems the proximate ancestor of the

latter aspect of the view. The vagueness, conveniently, makes Mencius?

doctrines fit it as well. The input is a perturbation from the outer world. The

output, the heart-mind?s action-guiding response, restores harmony to the

world and the inner state to tranquillity. If the inner state prior to the input

is not tranquil, the response will not restore harmony to the real situation.

Han Confucianism filled out this cosmic view of this black-box interaction

between heart-mind and world harmony using qi materialism. Qi is a rather more a

blend of energy and matter than pure matter?translations such as

"life-force" bring out an essential connection with vitality. This

makes it more appropriate for a cosmology that links the active heart-mind with

the changing world. Qi was the single constituting element of spirits and ghosts

as well. Wang Ch?ung?s skeptical, reductive application of qi theory focused

on shen (spirit-energy). He did not view its consequences for heart-mind as

particularly iconoclastic. It still lacked a notion of "consciousness"

independent of zhi (know). (Our zhi, he argued, stops when we are asleep and so

almost certainly it does when we are dead.) His arguments that nature had no

intentional purposes illustrated his reductive behaviorism?if it has neither

eyes nor ears, then it cannot have zhi (purposes or intentions). This argument

would hardly make sense if he had the familiar Western concept of consciousness.

Similarly, he argues that the five virtues are in the five organs so when the

organs are dead and gone, the virtues disappear with them. Return to Outline

Historical Developments: Buddhist Philosophy of Mind The next developments are

related to the introduction of Buddhist mental concepts into China. Most

accounts credit a movement dubbed "Neo-Taoism" with "paving the

way" for this radical change in philosophy of mind. Wangbi?s Neo-Taoist

system was explicitly a cosmology more than a theory of mind, but

interpretations tend to read it epistemically. Wangbi addressed the metaphysical

puzzle of the relation of being and non-being. (See YOU-WU) He postulated

non-being as the "basic substance." Non-being produced being. He

dubbed this obscure relationship as "substance and function."

Interpretations almost inevitably explain this on the analogy to Kant?s

Noumenon and Phenomenon. As noted, Wangbi had few epistemological interests, but

the analysis did have implications for heart-mind theory. He applied the

metaphysical scheme to his Confucian slogan?"Sage within, king

without." The mind was empty "within" while the behaviors were in

perfect conformity with the Confucian ritual dao. This tilts the Taoist

tradition toward the "emptiness" reading of the black-box analysis of

heart-mind. Wangbi also placed li (principle) in a more central explanatory

position. This paved the way for its use in translating Buddhism?s sentence or

law-like ?dharma?. It played roles in both Buddhist epistemology and theory

of mind. In sparse pre-Han usage, li was objective tendencies in thing-kinds.

(Intuitionists and naturalists took them to be the valid norm for that

kind?species relative bits of dao.) Wangbi gave it a more essentialist reading

in the context of the Book of Changes. He postulated a li guiding the mixtures

and transformations of yin and yang. One should be able to bypass the complexity

of the system by isolating and understanding its li. Buddhism introduced

revolutionary changes into Chinese heart-mind conceptual scheme. The original

Indo-European religion probably originated the familiar Western phenomenalism

(consciousness, experience-based mentalism). Indian philosophy came complete

with the familiar Western sentential analyses, mental content and cognitive

emphasis (belief and knowing-that). It even mimicked the subject-predicate

syllogism and the familiar epistemic and metaphysical subjective-objective

dualism. It introduced a semantic (eternal) truth predicate into Chinese thought

along with a representational view of the function of both mind and language.

Reason/intellect and emotion/desire formed a basic opposition in Buddhist

psychological analysis. An inner idea-world parallels (or replaces) the ordinary

world of objects. Soul and mind are roughly interchangeable and familiar

arguments for immortality suggest both metaphysical dualism and mental

transcendence or superiority over the physical. It conceptually links reality

(knowledge, reason) to permanence and appearance (illusion, experience) to

change. A universal chain of causation was a central explanatory device and a

mark of dependence and impermanence. Two caveats are in order, however. First,

although Buddhism introduced a dualist conceptual scheme, many schools

(arguably) denied the dualism so formulated and rejected any transcendent

?self?. Second, it is unclear how well the philosophy of mind was generally

understood and whether much of it actually "took" in China. One of the

early and notoriously unsuccessful schools was the "Consciousness

only" school (translated as "Only Heart-mind") which translated

the idealism of Yogacara Buddhism. The Yogacara analysis was Hume-like in

denying that anything linked the infinitesimal "moments of awareness"

into a real self. Scholars tend to blame its demise, however, as much on its

objectionable moral features (its alleged Hinayana or elitist failure to

guarantee universal salvation) as on its conceptual innovations. The most

successful schools were those that seemed to eschew theory of any kind?like

Zen (Ch?an) or Pure Land Buddhism?or those that opted for intuitive,

mystical simplicity (Tian T?ai and Hua Yen). The most important conceptual

legacy of Buddhism, therefore, seems to be the changed role and importance of

the character li (principle). In Buddhism it served a wide range of important

sentential and mental functions. It facilitated the translation of ?law?,

?truth?, and ?reason?. Neo-Confucianism would take it over (with

notoriously controversial implications) as key concept in its philosophy of

mind. Return to Outline Historical Developments: Neo-Confucianism

Neo-Confucianism is a Western name for a series of schools in which philosophy

of mind played a central role. Scholars (somewhat controversially) present these

schools as motivated by an anti-foreignism that sought to resurrect indigenous

classical systems. These had lain dormant for six-hundred odd years when the

freshness of Buddhism started to attract the attention of China’s intellectuals.

Resurrecting Confucianism required providing it with an alternative to Buddhist

metaphysics. For this, they drew on ch’i metaphysics, the black-box homeostasis

preserving analysis of heart-mind, Wang Pi’s and Buddhism’s li and Mencius’

classical theory of the inherent goodness of heart-mind. The intricacies of

Neo-Confucian systems are too rich to analyze in detail here. The earliest

versions focused on the notion of qi linkage between the heart-mind and the

world influenced by our action. They characterized the tranquil state of the

black-box as void. The school of li criticized that analysis as too Zen-like.

(This was a typical and damning charge to participants in this movement,

although a Zen period in one?s development of thought was a common pattern

among Neo-Confucians.) The li school insisted that any adequate account of

heart-mind had to give it an original moral content. It did this by postulating

an interdependent and inseparable dualism of li and qi. The li permeates the

heart and all of reality, which is composed of qi. The most tempting (and

common) elaboration uses the Platonic distinction of form and content, but that

analysis teeters on the edge of incoherence. The school fell back on dividing

the human mind from some transcendental or metaphysical Tao-mind. This made it

dubious as a theory of mind at all?in the ordinary sense. It essentially

became a metaphysics in which heart-mind was a cosmic force. One way of

understanding the motivation that drove the otherwise puzzling metaphysical

gymnastics links philosophy of mind and ethics. Neo-Confucians were searching

for the metaphysical system such that anyone so viewing the cosmos and one’s

place in it would reliably do what was right. The goal was having the

metaphysical outlook of the sage. The criterion of right and wrong was that the

sage’s mind would so judge it. If we could replicate the outlook, we would be

sage-like in our attitudes?including both beliefs and motivations. The effect

on motivation and behavior was more important than the theoretical coherence of

the system. The complexity of moral choice and human motivation required so many

perturbations into their account of the proposed system that it became an almost

infinitely flexible rationalization for intuitionism. Mencian optimism about

innate heart-mind dispositions proved an uncomfortable legacy. If human nature

and the heart-mind are innately and spontaneously moral, it was unclear why we

require such mental gymnastics to cultivate and condition the dispositions. They

portrayed the li as inherently good in all things, but somehow humans, alone in

all of nature, might fail to conform to its own natural norms. The attempt to

explain this via the li qi dualism flounders on the metaphysical principle that

the dualism pervades all things. Despite this well known (and intractable)

Confucian problem of evil, the school again became the Medieval orthodoxy.

Office holding required being able to parrot the view in considerable detail to

show their moral character. The school of Heart-mind was a rebellion against

that orthodoxy. We best understand this rival as a species of normative,

objective idealism. It saw the actual heart-mind as li and therefore inherently

good. The xin projects that li onto the world in the act of categorizing and